Tutorial 20 Existential Introduction.

6/19/07

Reading

Bergmann[2004] The Logic Book Section 10.1.

The Tutorial

There is a rule for adding a Existential Quantifier, Existential Introduction (also commonly known as 'Existential Generalization'). This permits the step illustrated by the following proof fragments.

 

5

Fa  
6

(∃x)Fx 5 ∃I

 

5

Fb  
6

(∃x)Fx 5 ∃I

 

5

(Fb&Gb)  
6

(∃z)(Fz&Gb) 5 ∃I

To understand what this rule permits, it helps to think about it as though you were going backwards from line 6 to line 5. Take the scope of line 6, which is Fx, Fx, and (Fz&Gb) respectively, then substitute a constant for free occurrences of the variable of quantification-- you should be able to get line 5, and indeed you can.

The Rule of Existential Introduction ∃I


If a derivation contains a line of the form

n. <formula>[<constant>/<variable>] <any justification>

then a line of the form

(∃<variable>)<formula> 'n ∃I'

may be added to the derivation.

Notice that, in a sense, you are generalizing on occurrences of the constant in the first formula. Now, you do not have to generalize on all of them; you can generalize on 0, 1, or many, depending on what is there and what you want to do.


Exercise to accompany Predicate Tutorial 10

Exercise 1 (of 1)

Proofs

Your browser is not displaying the Deriver applet. Try downloading Deriver itself by clicking on the link elsewhere on the page.

 

 

Derive the following

a) Fb∴(∃x)Fx

b) Fa∴(∃y)Fy

c) Fa∴(∃x)Fa

d) Fa,Ga∴(∃x)(Fx&Gx)

e) Fa,Ga∴(∃x)(Fx&Ga)

f) Fa,Ga∴(∃x)(Fa&Gx)

g) Fa,Ga∴(∃x)(Fx)&Ga